Review: Edward O.
Wilson, The Future of Life
(Little, Brown, 2002)
‘Although it is possible
to predict species extinction for the near future – say, over the next decade
or two – such a projection is impossible for the more distant future. The
obvious reason is that the trajectory depends on human choice. If the
decision were taken today to freeze all conservation efforts at their current
level while allowing the same rates of deforestation and other forms of
environmental destruction to continue, it is safe to say that at least a fifth
of the species of plants and animals would be gone or committed to early
extinction by 2030, and half by the end of the century. If, on the other hand, an all-out effort is made
to save the biologically richest parts of the natural world, the amount of
loss can be cut by at least half.’
– Edward O. Wilson, The Future of Life (pp. 101-2)
This is, I am obliged to
say right away, my first reading of a book by Edward O. Wilson. I can’t say it
is my first encounter, for I have met this name many times already. Wilson is
one of those prolific scientists whose presence and influence has grown far
beyond his area of specialization (myrmecology, the study of ants) and has
attained enough aura and eminence, within the mediations of spectacular
culture, to enable him to act as that rarity, a public intellectual: someone
whose views and assessments are widely disseminated and may actually count for
something in the deliberations of policymakers and even, perhaps, in the
formation of so-called public opinion.
I read this book to learn
more about the loss of biodiversity and the extinction of species. In
particular, I wanted to know what is behind Wilson’s assertion, often cited in
the literature around extinction, that if nothing is done to counteract current
trends, we can expect to lose half of all present life-forms by the end of the
twenty-first century. This book certainly clarifies his position and provides
all the evidence and steps that led him to this shocking prognosis. The gyst is
in the citation above, and I discuss Wilson’s prescriptions for the
conservation of global biodiversity at the end of this review.
Shasta salamander, threatened |
I have also learned that
the case of Edward O. Wilson is a complicated one, about which it won’t be
possible to reach anything like a just understanding, or even a fair
impression, by reading this one book. The Future of Life certainly sets out, in a lively and accessible
language, Wilson’s positions regarding biodiversity, extinction and
conservation – positions we need to know and wrestle with. His argumentation
here also invokes and sometimes actively intersects with his other output and
theoretical work, namely his more controversial theses concerning
‘sociobiology’, a new field Wilson is credited with initiating. As a
sociobiologist, Wilson insists that human behavior and society are based in
biology and heredity, unfolding according to evolutionary laws. Human nature,
as he uses the term here, is the long translation of species experience and
environmental conditioning into genetic code and memory. For Wilson,
sociobiology explains why, for example, studies consistently show that people
from across all classes and ethnic backgrounds prefer park-like landscapes that
combine groupings of trees with open spaces and vistas. We come from the
African savannahs, Wilson informs us, and have evolved as specialists in this
kind of environment.
How one handles the
balance between nature and nurture, heredity and culture, is obviously of
immense ethical and political consequence. I gather, from The Future of Life, that Wilson has highly developed and nuanced
positions on this, but there is not enough here for me to understand fully what
these positions are or to fathom exactly what Wilson may be packing into this
term ‘human nature’. To do that, I would presumably also have to read his Sociobiology:
The New Synthesis (Harvard, 1975),
On Human Nature (Harvard, 1979)
and Genes, Mind and Culture: the Coevolutionary Process (Harvard, 1981), as well as, perhaps, his most
recent The Social Conquest of Earth
(Liveright, 2012). And I might as well admit that, given the constraints of my
own economy of time and energy, this won’t be likely. So as a non-specialist
reader of Wilson, I will have to live with some uncomfortable uncertainty; the
many points of contact between his works, which are no doubt intended to cohere
in mutually-supporting ways, are not bridges I will be able to cross
confidently any time soon.
American burying beetle, endangered |
Clearly, these other
researches and theses are put to work in the notes and between the lines of The
Future of Life. Wilson’s passing
reprise here of his Biophilia
(Harvard, 1984), another work I should and perhaps will read, suggests that
there is substantial sociobiological support for the thesis that we humans love
and care for nature, even if we collectively are doing atrocious things to it:
‘It is not so difficult to love nonhuman life, if gifted with knowledge about
it. The capacity, even the proneness to do so, may well be one of the human
instincts. The phenomenon has been called biophilia, defined as the innate
tendency to focus upon life and lifelike forms, and in some instances to affiliate
with them emotionally’.(134)
We saw, in my review
posted earlier, that Shierry Weber Nicholson offers a psychoanalytic case for
the same conclusion. For Nicholsen, as a psychotherapist and critical theorist,
the balance comes down decisively on the side of nurture, culture and social
process. ‘Human nature’, if we have to use that term, may be constrained by
biology in certain ways, but social relations and behavior are mainly
historically constructed cultural sediments that remain open and changeable.
Wilson, as far as I can
read here, agrees that human nature is a dialectical process rather than simply
determined genetic code. But he clearly gives more weight to the continuous
effects of genetic programming by evolutionary processes. In view of the
biospheric meltdown and our urgent hopes to address it, the existence of a
shared, if blocked or repressed, proneness or tendency to bond with non-human
life forms may be a saving grace. Happily, it is less important how such a
‘love’ comes to be found in us than the fact that it exists as an embodied
capacity at all. The problem is largely the same, however it is formulated: how
do we unlock this love and let it operate freely? How do we help it fully to
become guiding ethos and actualized social practice? Even if Wilson’s
explanation proves more correct, such a biophilia is in itself clearly
insufficient in preventing a disastrous extinction event. Even if it is an
instinct, such a love needs social support. How to provide this support and
open the needed pathways for its mobilizing expression and performance?
Golden toad, extinct since 1989 |
The following passages
convey a sense of how Wilson handles this dialectic of ‘human nature’ (or as
Adorno would say, ‘natural history’.) Noting that environmentalism is still
widely viewed as a ‘special-interest lobby’ rather than an appropriate response
to a survival threat, Wilson offers some thoughts about why our innate
biophilia may be inadequate:
‘The relative indifference
to the environment springs, I believe, from deep within human nature. The human
brain evidently evolved to commit itself emotionally only to a small piece of
geography, a limited band of kinsmen, and two or three generations into the
future. To look neither far ahead nor far afield is elemental in a Darwinian
sense.... The reason is simple: it is a hard-wired part of our Paleolithic
heritage. For hundreds of millennia those who worked for short-term gain within
a small circle of relatives and friends lived longer and left more offspring –
even when their collective striving caused their chiefdoms and empires to
crumble around them. The long view that might have saved their distant
descendants required a vision and extended altruism instinctively difficult to
marshal.’(40)
At the same time, Wilson
insists that the bisopheric crisis is an ethical test we are capable of rising
up to: ‘The great dilemma of environmental reasoning stems from this conflict
between short-term and long-term values. To select values for the near future
of one’s own tribe or country is relatively easy. To select values for the
distant future of the whole planet is also relatively easy – in theory at
least. To combine the two visions to create a universal environmental ethic is,
on the other hand, very difficult. But combine them we must, because a
universal environmental ethic is the only guide by which humanity and the rest
of life can be safely conducted through the bottleneck into which our species
has foolishly blundered.’(40-1)
Coral reef bleaching, Australia |
Biophilia in any case is
not simply deterministic. If it highlights a certain tendency in the dialectic
of nature and nurture, there are antagonistic tendencies, such as biophobia, as
well. But some slippages also find their way into Wilson’s usually careful
argumentation: ‘To say that there is an instinct, or more accurately an array
of instincts, that can be labeled biophilia is not to imply that the brain is
hardwired. We do not ambulate like robots to the nearest lakeshore meadow.
Instead, the brain is predisposed to acquire certain preferences as opposed to
others. Psychologists who study mental development say that we are hereditarily
prepared to learn certain
behaviors and counterprepared
to learn others.’(137) Do psychologists really claim this predisposition is hereditary
– that is, genetic? Are they even trained and competent to do so? Is
their position not rather that it is social? Moreover, Wilson’s rejection of hardwiring here
flies in the face of his invocation of it earlier, in the passage cited above.
I guess these and other nitpicking questions would be resolved by reading the
fuller treatments Wilson gives elsewhere.
Still, such questions beg
others more general but no less crucial, which I can only hope to register
here. These point to the difficulties and challenges of translation among the
different discourses compelled to intersect on the field of ecocide. In short,
how do we talk to each other about this urgent threat from our multitudinously
divergent subject positions, disciplines and languages? How do we share our
experiences, researches, knowledge, and proposals, as well as our feelings,
fears and hopes? We will need to hear and listen to each other carefully, if
only to understand views and programs we won’t, in the end, be able to accept.
It will be crucial for scientists to share their findings and predictions with
us, in ways that convey their conclusions and at least a basic sense of the
process by which they were reached, without compromising complexities and
qualifications. ‘Popular science’, basically a genre of translation, will of
necessity be a rapidly expanding field. We will need to be fast learners in
this, for we cannot take it on trust that policymakers and politicians are
making honest and careful use of science, rather than instrumentalizing it in
opportunistic and cynical ways. Nor can we take it for granted that the
scientists will always have the forums to speak for themselves and expose such
manipulations, or that such exposures will suffice to arrest powerful social
tendencies. (Remember the experience of the Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists.)
Moreover, we cannot forget that the autonomy of modernist science is an ideal
seldom matched by social fact. Its tendency to merge with business, state and
war machine has deeply corrupted whole fields of research and development.
Dying coral |
Reading Edward O. Wilson,
I readily admit I have come to like him. His intelligence is warm and
expansive, and his quirks are by and large charming. He begins the book rather
daringly, with a prologue to Thoreau, and the opening sentence is a single word
of emphatic address: ‘Henry!’ But despite the rhetorical seduction and my growing
readerly trust in Wilson’s own biolphilia, there are moments when the sheer
difference of some his assumptions suddenly rears up like a concrete wall.
Wilson may study ants, but he also thinks big, on a large and technocratic
scale, glibly juggling very large numbers in discussions of, for example, the
‘bottleneck’ of population growth and planetary carrying capacity:
‘The bottom line is
different from that generally assumed by our leading economists and public
philosophers. They have ignored the numbers that count. Consider that with the
global population past six billion and on its way to eight billion or more by
mid-century, per-capita fresh water and arable land are descending to levels
resource experts agree are risky. The ecological footprint – the average amount
of productive land and shallow sea appropriated by each person in bits and
pieces from around the world for food, water, housing, energy, transportation,
commerce and waste absorption – is about one hectare (2.5 acres) in developing
nations but about 9.6 hectares (24 acres) in the United States. The footprint
for the total human population is 2.1 hectares (5.2 acres). For every person in
the world to reach present US levels of consumption with existing technology
would require four more planet Earths. The five billion people of the
developing countries may never wish to attain this level of profligacy. But in
trying to achieve at least a decent standard of living, they have joined the
industrial world in erasing the last of the natural environments.’(23)
Unquestionably, the scale
of our problems is this large, and acknowledging so does not necessarily entail
Malthusian conclusions. But where a critical theorist understands these ‘social
facts’ as the postcolonial fruits of a dominant logic that has thoroughly
shaped the forms and uses of technology, Wilson sees rather the opportunity for
grand techno-fixes: ‘Science and technology, combined with a lack of
self-understanding and a Paleolithic obstinacy, brought us to where we are
today. Now science and technology, combined with foresight and moral courage,
must see us through the bottleneck and out.’(Ibid.)
In the concluding chapter,
under the openly immodest title ‘The Solution’, Wilson offers some
clear-sighted proposals for the global conservation of biodiversity. But his
indications about how such proposals would be realized, against the pressures
that are driving deforestation, extraction, over-harvesting and so on, reveal a
very naïve and inadequate conception of the social process. It becomes clear by
the end of the book that Wilson’s outlook is basically technocratic and
melioristically progressive. He concludes that science and technology can save
us, but only if wielded expertly and powerfully from above, in an alliance of
‘the three secular stanchions of civilized existence: government, the private
sector and science and technology’.(164) Wilson is cautiously optimistic,
because, after all: ‘Science and technology are themselves reason for
optimism.’(156) Moreover: ‘A growing cadre of leaders in business, government,
and religion now think in this foresighted manner. They understand that
humanity is in a bottleneck of overpopulation and wasteful consumption. They
agree, at least in principle, that we will have to maneuver carefully in order
to pass through the bottleneck safely.’(157) Above all, it is the NGOs who will
mediate the conflicts and step in decisively where politicians fear to tread.
Wilson’s new Platonic
philosopher-kings will apparently form a global vanguard of biophilic
technocrats capable of bestriding a public sphere of governments, responsible
corporations and NGOs. The decisions of this elite are apparently expected,
moreover, to be endorsed by the masses through the mediations of democracies
that function unproblematically and the brave new virtualities of Web 2.0. The
more ominous social trends of the last sixty years are evidently lost on
Wilson. He seems unaware that the knottings of capital, science and technocracy
are deeply implicated in a general corruption of democratic processes and the
rise, since 1945, of the secretive national security-surveillance state. Is it
really possible to imagine that all is well with the forms of contemporary
governance?
The possibility of or need
for a self-rescuing change from below seems not to register – or if it does, is
treated in troublingly condescending manner: ‘At the risk of seeming
politically correct, I will now close with a tribute to protest groups. [He
chuckles:] They gather like angry bees at meetings of the World Trade
Organization, the World Bank, and the World Economic Forum.’(188) Hmmm. Aren’t
these institutions the very places where the enlightened biophilic elites are presumably
meeting to save us? Seriously now: ‘The protest groups are the early warning
system for the natural economy. They are the living world’s immunological
response.’(Ibid.) But of course, these antibodies should behave themselves. If
a few of them destroy property, clash with the police or otherwise get out of
hand, then ‘they deserve fines and jail terms.’(189) Do they deserve pepper
spray, tear gas, tasers, beatings and rubber bullets, too? Again, this is a
shockingly clichéd view of politics and the social process. As brilliant as he
is in many areas, he has not grasped the basics of the social force-field. His
call for an eco-ethics seems to be grounded in the benign assumption that
changes in behavior must surely follow knowledge and understanding, so long as
the called-for behavior is not in conflict with instinct. But what if they are
in conflict with the dominant and enforced social logic, as is here the case?
If Wilson is sanguine
about the gap between science and policymakers, this is because, for him, both
belong to the guild of enlightened technocracy. The main problem ‘is how to
raise the poor to a decent standard of living worldwide while preserving as
much of the rest of life as possible’.(189) Once our ethical, biophilic
technocrats understand the problem, they can be trusted to engineer and carry
out the solutions, tout va bien.
From the perspectives of critical theory, such a daydream is more than naïve;
it betrays some dangerous misrecognitions. For me, Wilson’s handling of the
social process and the relation between capitalist accumulation and biospheric
meltdown seems as amateurish as my handling of the science would, I’m sure, seem
to him. My own responses and discomforts here remind me that the gap between
science and politics is not the only one we have to worry about. The gap
between science and critical theory opens so wide in places that the old
specter of incommensurability returns to haunt the encounter.
As we have seen, Wilson is
only very weakly self-reflective about the historic role and social position of
science, and he never inquires about the social logic that captures and shapes
technology qua forces of production. He evidently hasn’t heard of critical
theory, or perhaps has decided not to dignify it with attempts at refutation.
With astonishing ease, he simply disavows the critique of automatic progress
and reaffirms his eighteenth-century faith in the noble impulses of science – as
if science was free and its impulses sufficient to rein in and steer the very
social logic that dominates it. We only need ‘to diagnose and disconnect
extraneous political ideology, then shed it in order to move toward the common
ground where economic progress and conservation are treated as one and the same
goal’.(155) Is it really still news, that ideology constitutes and saturates
the social and hence is not simply ‘extraneous’ and ‘disconnectable’; or that
value-neutrality, already thoroughly critiqued before World War II and
Hiroshima (for example, by Horkheimer in 1937), is an ideological position?
In addition to Wilson’s
technocratic reflexes, the basically neo-liberal assumptions that correspond to
them also come into view as he introduces his Solution. In some ways, Wilson
does indeed propose some radical transformations in the human relation to the
biosphere. But these are expected to take place within good old ‘there is no
alternative’ parameters. Well, we are revealed by what we always already
exclude: ‘The world economy is now propelled by venture capital and technical
innovation; it cannot be returned to a pastoral civilization.’(156) Is that the
only choice: the continued rule of venture capital or past models of
pastorality? Might there not be new models of cohabitation based on new,
emerging productive values and practices, such as permaculture? Might not a mix
of models promise to be more humane and sustainable than capitalist
monoculture? ‘Nor will any socialism return in a second attempt to rescue us,
at least not in any form resembling the Soviet model.’(Ibid.) No one wants
another attempt at technocratic state socialism on that model, but, again, is
this really our only choice: capitalism or that? Encore en effort, Professor Wilson!
But now he explains: ‘The
juggernaut of technology-based capitalism will not be stopped. Its momentum is
reinforced by the billions of poor people in developing countries anxious to
participate in order to share the material wealth of the industrialized nations.’(156)
Here we at least have the bones of an argument to go with the assertion. But it
isn’t just the poor, is it? I might have put it differently, but Wilson does
validly point here to our deep implication, through our desires and
participation in the fantasies and enjoyments on offer, in a system that cannot
deliver what it promises (at least, not without ‘four more planet Earths’.) So:
‘The choice is clear: the juggernaut will very soon either chew up what remains
of our living world, or it will be redirected to save it.’ Science, technology,
NGOs and enlightened technocratic despots to the rescue.
Rainforest activist José Cláudio Ribeiro da Silva, assassinated in Brazil, 2011 |
I could go on in this
vein, but let me stop here. Wilson lays out, with great clarity, the ecological
dynamics of the biospheric meltdown and mass extinction, and we should be
grateful to him for that. We will have to accept that his handling of the
social dynamics driving meltdown and extinction is flawed and inadequate. Only
massive pressure from below, opposing the pressures of accumulation that operate
routinely, is likely to open the spaces for technocratic policymakers to act
autonomously, in the ways Wilson calls for. The current austerity programs are
proof enough that the technocratic establishment is unprepared to think or act
beyond the given logic of rivalrous accumulation, whatever the immediate cost
in public destruction and misery. The current conjuncture also unhappily
confirms that we all, collectively, are not yet willing to risk a bold and
robust break with the given logic, either. So-called politics is stuck in the
untenable but persistent hope that by more belt-tightening we can somehow
return to the commodified miracles of the post-1945 economic expansion. Expansion
itself is still not in doubt. As for the biospheric meltdown, neither we nor
the technocrats have even begun to take that seriously into political account.
Nevertheless, Wilson’s
proposals are noble enough, and as goals are entirely worthy. If we fully
implement them, he thinks we should be able to reduce the loss of life forms
from roughly fifty-percent by 2100 to twenty-five percent. Here are the
highlights: Wilson points to twenty-five hotspots of biodiversity that require
urgent immediate protection; these habitats, mostly endangered remnants of
rainforest, ‘are both at the greatest risk and shelter the largest
concentrations of species found nowhere else’.(161) Next, the five remaining
frontier forests, including Amazonia and the conifer forests of Canada, Alaska,
Russia, Finland and Scandanavia, must be protected and kept intact. Next, all
logging of old-growth forests everywhere must cease immediately. The marine
hotspots of the world, above all the coral reefs, must be defined precisely and
assigned ‘the same action priority as for those on the land’.(162) The mapping
and scientific description of the world’s biodiversity must be completed.
Conservation must be made profitable: ‘Find ways to raise the income of those
who live in and near the reserves. Give them a proprietary interest in the
natural environment and engage them professionally in its protection.’(Ibid.)
More restoration projects. More breeding of endangered species in zoos and
botanical gardens. And finally: ‘Support population planning.’(164)
Wilson offers some numbers
to argue that these goals are not unreasonable or asking too much: ‘For global
conservation, only one-thousandth of the current annual world domestic product,
or $30 billion out of approximately $30 trillion, would accomplish most of the
task. One key element, the protection and management of the world’s existing
natural reserves, could be financed by a one-cent-per-cup tax on coffee.’(Ibid)
Who would not pay another penny for a cup of coffee! One can only agree with
Wilson, that given the stakes, conservation of biodiversity represents ‘the best
bargain humanity has ever been offered’.(Ibid)
Wilson puts his immediate
hopes in the conservation NGO’s, which have now become sufficiently large and
deep-pocketed to buy endangered habitat outright, or else compete for leases
with global extraction industries and mediate debt-for-habitat swaps between
banks and cash-strapped small countries. The bigger the better here, Wilson
insists, praising the efforts of Conservation International, Wildlife
Conservation Society, Nature Conservancy, and World Wildlife Fund (of whose
board of directors Wilson was a member for ten years).
Funeral of Ribeiro da Silva and Maria do Espirito Santa, 2011 |
Wilson does his best to
inspire us with success stories that point to what’s possible. By the last
page, I want to give him a hug. And I may even be moved to write a check or two
to a land-buying, reserve-building NGO, in addition to more activist groups
such as Sea Shepherd. But we cannot duck the fact that Wilson’s approach
remains over-optimistic, so long as the social and psychological obstacles to
self-rescue have not been confronted more radically. Wilson’s proposals are
admirable and achievable. Why, then, have they not been implemented? (In 2011, environmental activists around the world were murdered at a rate of one a week. This
morning a new study informs us that half of the coral cover in Australia’s
Great Barrier Reef has now been lost.) The social returns, like every
repressed. By all means, let us push for conservation. More reserves, more
sanctuaries, stronger protections. Extinction, as the slogan goes, is forever.
But we will also have to push against the master logic that blocks us, even in
this modest and reasonable goal of conserving precious biodiversity.
Critical theory suggests
that as we hope to change ourselves, we need to struggle and be ready to keep struggling
against the social forms of domination. We need to organize continuous and
growing pressure on the policymakers and technocrats, but we cannot wait for
them to change directions and finally adopt the values Wilson already credits
them with. At the same time, we ourselves need to change everyday life by
opening and following lines of flight that enable us to actualize our values
now. The double strategy from below – political struggle and building our new
commons day by day – cannot promise an instant fix. But these are efforts that
slowly shift the balance of forces. By such a shift, and probably only by such
a shift, can we realistically hope that the hold and global headlock of the
master logic will at some point give way to something new and better. What will
be left of the wild on that day, if Wilson’s estimates of the rate of
extinction hold, will be a heartbreaking question to answer.
GR
Isabella Kirkland, Endangered and Extinct Species |
No comments:
Post a Comment